This paper appears in full as
Roth, Alvin E. and Xiaolin Xing "Turnaround Time and Bottlenecks in Market Clearing: Decentralized Matching in the Market for Clinical Psychologists," Journal of Political Economy, 105, April 1997, 284-329.

copyright 1997 by the University of Chicago, all rights reserved.

What follows (with permission [#47508] from University of Chicago Press) is almost the complete text, excepting only a figure. Some mathematical notation has been adapted to html (e.g. here "mu" is written, rather than the Greek letter of that name). Careful readers should consult the printed version.


Turnaround Time and Bottlenecks in Market Clearing: Decentralized Matching in the Market for Clinical Psychologists

By Alvin E. Roth, Department of Economics, and Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard University and

Xiaolin Xing, Department of Economics and Statistics, National University of Singapore

Revised: August 22, 1996


Abstract: In the context of entry-level labor markets, we consider the potential transactions which have to be evaluated before equilibrium transactions can be identified. These potential transactions involve offers which are rejected. After an initial phase in which many offers can be proffered in parallel, subsequent potential transactions must be processed serially, since a new offer cannot be made until an outstanding offer is rejected. In this phase even a small time required to process offers and rejections may cause bottlenecks. In many, perhaps most, decentralized labor markets, this means that transactions have to be finalized before there is time for the market to clear, i.e. before all of the potential transactions which would need to be evaluated in order to reach a stable outcome can in fact be evaluated. This has implications for the strategic behavior of firms and workers. In particular, in deciding to whom to offer a position, a firm may have strong incentives to consider not only its preferences over workers, but also the likelihood that its offer will be accepted, since if its offer is rejected it may find that many other potential employees have become unavailable in the interim. The analysis is carried out in connection with the decentralized market for clinical psychologists. The implications for other kinds of markets are considered.


Acknowledgements: This work was partially supported by NSF Grant No. SES-9121968. We are indebted to many people for information about the clinical psychology market, including Michael Carifio, Sue Campbell, Marsha Marcus, Ivan Mensh, Bob Perloff, Paul Pilkonis, Carl Zimet, and a number of participants in the market who wished to remain anonymous. We have also received useful advice from Vince Crawford, Jean Francois Richard, and Uri Rothblum.


This paper studies the procedures used to control and coordinate the timing of transactions in the (American) entry level market for clinical psychologists. Transactions in this market are supposed to all be made by telephone on "Selection Day," which is presently the second Monday in February, from 9:00 AM to 4:00 PM Central Standard Time. The rules require that no offers be made before 9:00 AM, and that all offers made during the course of the market and not yet rejected must remain open until 4:00 PM. That is, both early offers and "exploding offers" (which require a decision before the end of the market) are not allowed. (The detailed rules, given in Appendix 1, will be discussed later.)

Subject to many modifications of its rules, this kind of decentralized but uniform timing regime has been in use in this market since 1973. One kind of modification has concerned the length of the market, which is now only seven hours. In the early 1970's the market lasted five days, and was subsequently shortened to three, and for most of the 1980's the rules specified that the market would take place from 8:00 AM Monday until Noon the following day. This concern with the amount of time which the market (and individual offers) should remain open is one that has been observed in many markets, and we will consider why this is important.

We will also compare the organization of this market with the more centralized organization of entry level markets for American physicians (Roth 1984, 1996). One reason this comparison arises is that over the last twenty years clinical psychologists have considered whether their own market might be better organized if they adopted the procedures used by physicians (see Roth and Xing 1994). The comparison is natural, since there is a sense in which the procedures employed in these markets are very similar. However, we will see that these apparently similar procedures operate very differently.

In both of these analyses--of the time which the market remains open and of the comparison between the organization of the markets for psychologists and for physicians--it will turn out that a critical variable is the length of time it takes for an offer to be rejected and a new offer made. In the clinical psychology market all interviewing is completed well before Selection Day, and because all participants come prepared to spend the day by the telephone, this time is extraordinarily short. Based on our (limited) site observations we have roughly approximated it as requiring only six minutes: only one minute for an offer to be rejected, and only five minutes for a new offer to be conveyed to another candidate. We will see that even this quick turnaround time creates bottlenecks, because, during much of the time the market operates, offers must be processed serially, rather than in parallel.

We will argue that many markets, like the psychology market, go through an initial phase in which many potential transactions can be proffered and considered in parallel, but that eventually a high proportion of the potential transactions that remain have to be proffered and considered serially. It is in this latter phase that the turnaround time becomes the rate determining factor 1. It will also become apparent from our analysis that the amount of time a market remains open cannot be evaluated independently of the turnaround time required for an offer to be rejected and a new one issued. A market which is open for, say, one hundred times as long as the psychology market but which has a turnaround time longer than 10 hours (100 x 6 minutes) would in a critical sense be open for a shorter effective time 2.

I. Institutions related to timing

In Roth and Xing (1994) we argued that one function of a market is to establish a time at which large numbers of buyers and sellers can plan to make transactions, but that establishing such a time can be difficult. We considered several dozen markets and submarkets which had experienced considerable difficulty in establishing a time at which transactions would take place. Most of these markets were annual entry-level professional labor markets which had gone through a period in which, year after year, transactions were made earlier and earlier, often in a way which made the market at any moment very thin. In some cases this unraveling of transaction times proceeded to the point where employers were hiring new employees up to two years before they would complete their professional qualifications and begin work. However, many markets which experienced such difficulties subsequently developed institutions to alleviate them. A number of markets around the world--for physicians, dentists, lawyers, and (recently) for osteopaths--have adopted centralized market clearing institutions which are organized roughly along the lines of the deferred acceptance algorithm, described next 3.

The centralized part of such a market begins after applicants and employers have contacted and interviewed one another in the usual (decentralized) way. Each applicant then submits to a centralized clearinghouse a rank ordering, in order of preference, of each employer with which he has interviewed 4. Similarly, each employer submits a rank ordering of all the applicants they have interviewed. (Leaving an applicant or employer off the preference list means that the worker or job is unacceptable.) These preference lists are then processed by an algorithm to produce a matching of applicants to positions.

Roth (1984, 1991) showed that the algorithms used in a number of the successful centralized market clearing mechanisms are approximately the same as the deferred acceptance procedure first formally studied by Gale and Shapley (1962), which produces a matching of job seekers to jobs that is stable in terms of the submitted preferences, in the sense that no student and hospital who are not matched to each other would prefer to be so matched 5. In the deferred acceptance algorithm, each employer begins by offering each of its positions to the candidates at the top of its preference list, i.e. if it has k identical positions, it offers them to its top k candidates. Each candidate rejects any unacceptable offers, and any candidate who has received more than one offer rejects all but the most preferred (highest ranked) of these, which is held without commitment. Following any rejections, each firm offers the position to its next highest ranked candidate who hasn't yet rejected it, so long as acceptable candidates remain. Each candidate who gets new offers compares them with any offer he may be holding, and again rejects all but the most preferred. The procedure stops when no firm wishes to make any further offers, at which point each candidate accepts (and is matched to) the position (if any) that he is holding. Gale and Shapley (1962) showed that the matching produced by this procedure is a stable matching, and that when all agents have strict preferences it is firm-optimal among the stable matchings, in the sense that no firm prefers any other stable matching.

In a centralized clearinghouse, the matching is performed by computer, using the preference lists submitted by the participants. We will now turn to the clinical psychology market, and see that it uses a very similar procedure, carried out not in a centralized way by computer, but in a decentralized way, over the telephone network. And the procedure used in the psychology market terminates in a very different way, and at a different matching than the deferred acceptance procedure, and this in turn has implications for the strategies and incentives facing the participants.

A. The market for clinical psychologists

1. Market rules, and their evolution over time

Clinical psychologists are employed as interns just prior to completing their doctoral training, and/or as postdocs just after completing it. In recent years the market for these positions has involved just over 2,000 positions a year, offered at about 500 sites (see Roth and Xing 1994 and the references there). As noted earlier, uniform timing regimes have been mandated in this market since 1973, with a gradual shortening of the time the market is supposed to remain open, to its present length of seven hours. The organization created to administer the market is the Association for Psychology Postdoctoral and Internship Centers (APPIC). The APPIC rules for the 1993 market are given in the Appendix.

The basic market structure is given by rules 3 through 6. Rules 3 and 4 control the timing of the market. Rules 5 and 6 specify that, while the market is open, offers will be made and rejected according to a decentralized version of the deferred acceptance procedure. As in the case of the market for physicians, the salaries and general job descriptions associated with positions are specified in advance, and are not variable parts of the offers.

Many of the rules contain additional clauses, added over time in response to complaints about how the rules are stretched or broken. (Examining the rules, and how they change over time, is one of the best ways to gain insight into the operation of a market.) One complaint is that applicants are subjected to a great deal of informal pressure to indicate in advance whether they will accept an offer, i.e. to indicate in advance whether a particular employer is their first choice (see Rule 3c). This is also a common complaint in centralized matching procedures (see Roth 1984 and 1991), but in this decentralized market it has additional force. In the centralized markets, where matching is done by computer, it is not uncommon for students who feel unfairly pressured to say that they will rank some program first to say so, but then not do so. However in the psychology market, to say that you will rank some program first is tantamount to a promise that when they call you on selection day, you will accept their offer immediately. The virtually face-to-face nature of the telephone interaction, coupled with the fact that many psychology sub-markets are small worlds, make this a difficult promise to renege on 6.

2. A site visit

To put various kinds of behavior into perspective, it may help to recount the situation at an internship program we visited on selection day in 1993. This program had 5 positions, and received 200 inquiries which turned into 71 completed applications. Invitations were issued to 30 candidates to come for interviews, and 29 accepted. On the morning of selection day, the two program co-directors, who would make the calls, came equipped with a rank ordered list of 20 acceptable candidates from among those interviewed. The rank ordering was obtained from polling the psychologists on the staff, and it was understood that the co- directors had discretion about how to use it 7. Prior to selection day, about half a dozen of the candidates had indicated that the program in question was their first choice, and that they would accept an offer immediately if one were made 8.

On selection day the codirectors said their general strategy was "don't tie up offers with people who will hold them all day." They therefore decided to make their first offers (for their 5 positions) to numbers 1, 2, 3, 5, and 12 on their rank order list, with the rationale being that numbers 3, 5, and 12 had indicated that they would accept immediately, and that 1 and 2 were so attractive as to be worth taking chances on 9. Two phones were used to make these calls, starting precisely at 9:00 am CST. Candidates 3, 5, and 12 accepted immediately, as promised. Candidate 1 was reached at 9:05 (on the fourth attempt, after three busy signals) and held the offer, until 9:13 when he called back to reject it. During this period, an incoming call (on a third phone whose number had been given to candidates) was received from the candidate ranked 8th, who now said that the program was her first choice. She was thanked and told she was still under consideration, and when candidate 1 called to reject the offer he was holding, the codirectors decided to make the next offer to candidate 8 (and not to number 4, as initially planned 10.). The offer to number 8 was then made and accepted immediately, and while that phone call was in progress, an incoming call from candidate 2 informed them that she had accepted another position. The decision was then made to offer the remaining position next to the highest ranked remaining candidate who had indicated he would accept immediately, number 10, and this offer was accepted at 9:21. After the briefest of celebrations, the codirectors called the remaining candidates to inform them that all positions were filled. These calls were completed by 9:35, 35 minutes after the opening of the market. The five positions were filled with the candidates initially ranked 3, 5, 8, 10, and 12.

Three things to note about this episode, which does not seem to be atypical, are the directors' concern not to make offers which ran the risk of being rejected late in the day, the consequent attention they paid to candidates who had indicated they would immediately accept an offer from the program, and the willingness of candidates to convey such information. Note also that the time required to process offers is very short. In what follows, we will analyze some computer simulations of the market, which show that even this short time has large consequences. But first we present some formal analysis which will provide a framework for comparison of these centralized and decentralized market institutions.

II. Comparison of centralized and decentralized markets, of different lengths

Several kinds of comparisons will be made in this section. Part A begins with some theoretical results comparing decentralized and centralized matching, in markets which may differ in length. We can make welfare comparisons among different institutions, but these theoretical results do not allow us to predict the magnitudes of the welfare effects, which depend on the effective length of the market.

To consider magnitudes, we turn to simulation. The analytical results reveal that the welfare comparisons will come into play only when markets are too short to fully clear. Since this depends both on the duration of the market and on how long it takes to make offers and accept and reject them (and hence how many transactions can be considered in the course of the market), it might be that when transaction times are very short (as in the psychology market) there will be no difference between centralized and decentralized market clearing. However, the simulations will demonstrate clearly that even short transaction times have very large effects.

The APPIC rules provide an unambiguous institutional structure for the simulations. The relatively arbitrary assumptions that must be made will be those concerning the joint distribution of preferences of firms and workers. Section B will compare markets with and without fixed termination times, and different behavioral assumptions about the participants, under the assumption that the preferences of different firms and workers are uncorrelated. Section C will then consider the sensitivity of the results obtained to different assumptions about preferences (as well as to different concentrations of positions among firms), and show that the principal results of Section B are robust.

It will help to keep in mind several differences between the centralized deferred acceptance algorithm and the decentralized procedure outlined in the APPIC rules. In a centralized market, participants must decide what preference lists to submit, after which offers, acceptances, and rejections are carried out automatically. But in the psychology market participants don't submit preference lists; instead they can decide after each phone call what to do next, and random events can determine the order in which offers are made, as when more than one firm attempts to telephone the same candidate at the same time, and only one can get through. Also, when offers expire at 4:00 PM, workers essentially must accept whatever offer they are holding (see rule 4d) 11. And (unlike in the centralized market), when the organized part of the market ends there may still be unmatched firms and workers who already know that they would prefer to be matched to one another, so the aftermarket in the decentralized case is very much a continuation of the original market, except with exploding offers which must be accepted (or rejected) immediately 12.

A. Random matchings, termination times, and aftermarkets: some formal analysis

1. An analytical framework: definitions and notation

For the static elements of our model, in which a firm may employ several workers, but a worker may work for no more than one firm, we use the "college admissions" model as reformulated in Roth (1985) and Roth and Sotomayor (1990, chapter 5). The first elements of this model are two finite and disjoint sets, F = {F1, ..., Fn} and W={w1, ..., wm}, of firms and workers. For each firm F, there is a positive integer qF, which indicates the number of (identical) positions F has to offer, that is, the maximum number of positions it may fill. (When we denote a particular firm by Fi, its quota of positions will be denoted qi.)

An outcome is a matching of workers to firms, such that each worker is matched to at most one firm, and each firm is matched to at most its quota of workers. It will be convenient to denote a firm that has some number of unfilled positions as matched to itself in each of those positions, and similarly an unmatched worker will be matched to herself. To give a formal definition, we first define for any set X an unordered family of elements of X to be a collection of elements, not necessarily distinct, in which the order is immaterial.

We can now define a matching mu to be a function from the set F [union] W into the set of unordered families of elements of F [union] W such that (1) |mu(w)| = 1 for every worker w and mu(w) = w if mu (w) [is not an element of] F; (2) |mu(F)| = q f for every firm F; and if the number of workers in mu(F), say r, is less than qF, then mu(F) contains qF - r copies of F; and (3) mu(w) = F if and only if w is in mu(F). So mu(w1) = F denotes that worker w1 is employed at firm F at the matching mu, and mu(F) = {w1, w3, F, F} denotes that firm F, with quota qF = 4, employs workers w1 and w3 and has two positions unfilled.

Each worker has preferences over the firms (and the possibility of remaining unmatched in the market), and each firm has preferences over the workers (and the possibility of leaving a position unfilled). All preferences are transitive. We will write Fi > wFj to indicate that worker w prefers Fi to Fj, and Fi [greater than or equal to]w wFj to indicate that w likes Fi at least as well as Fj. Similarly, wi > Fwj and wi [greater than or equal to]F wj represent firm F's preferences P(F) over individual workers. Firm F is acceptable to worker w if F [is greater than or equal to]w w, and worker w is acceptable to firm F if w [is greater than or equal to]FF, i.e. an acceptable firm is one which is preferable to being unmatched, and an acceptable worker is one which the firm prefers to leaving a position unfilled.

Each worker's preferences over alternative matchings correspond exactly to her preferences over her own assignments at the two matchings. Things are not quite so simple for firms, because even though we have described firms' preferences over workers, each firm with a quota greater than 1 must be able to compare groups of workers in order to compare alternative matchings. It will be sufficient for our purposes to assume merely that a firm's preferences over groups of employees it could be matched with (i.e. over groups of not more than qF workers) are such that, for any two assignments that differ in only one worker, it prefers the assignment containing the more preferred worker (and is indifferent between them if it is indifferent between the workers). Any preferences of this sort are called responsive to the firm's preferences over individual workers (Roth, 1985)

A matching mu is individually irrational if mu(w) = F for some worker w and firm F such that either the worker is unacceptable to the firm or the firm is unacceptable to the worker. Such a matching will also be said to be blocked by the unhappy agent. This reflects that the rules of the market allow every agent to withhold consent from such a match. Similarly, a firm F and worker w will be said together to block a matching mu if they are not matched to one another at mu, but would both prefer to be matched to one another than to (one of) their present assignments. That is, mu is blocked by the firm-worker pair (F,w) if mu(w) [does not equal] F and if F >wmu(w) and w >F sigma for some sigma in mu(F). (Note that sigma may equal either some worker w' in mu(F), or, if one of firm F's positions is unfilled at mu(F), sigma may equal F.) Matchings blocked in this way by an individual or by a pair of agents are unstable in the sense that there are agents with both the incentive (because preferences are responsive) and the power (under rules which allow any firm and worker to conclude an agreement with each other) to disrupt such matchings. So we can now define a matching mu to be stable if it is not blocked by any individual or any firm-worker pair 13.

Gale and Shapley (1962) showed that the set of stable matchings is always non-empty. Furthermore, when no agent is indifferent between any two mates, there exists for each side of the market (F or W) a stable matching (muF or muW) that is optimal for that side, in the sense that no agent on that side of the market prefers any other stable matching.

To consider random matching processes, we extend this framework slightly 14. Define a random matching to be a random variable whose range is the set of all matchings. For each random matching mu we obtain random variables mu(v) for each agent v in F [union] W, where each mu(v) is the (random) assignment of v under mu. (The range of mu(v) is v [union] F if v is in W, or v [union] W if v is in F.)

Given two random matchings mu1 and mu2 and a worker w with preferences Pw over F [union] w, we say that mu2(w) stochastically Pw-dominates mu1(w), (and write mu2 >>w mu1) if, for every v in F [union] {w}, Pr{mu2(w) >w v } [is greater or equal to] Pr{mu1(w) >w v}; that is, for any level of satisfaction the probability that w's match exceeds that level of satisfaction is greater under the random matching mu2 than under mu1. So if mu2 >>w mu1 then any utility maximizer with ordinal preferences Pw prefers mu2(w) to mu1(w).

2. Decentralized deferred acceptance with random elements and termination time (with and without an aftermarket):

Figure 1 presents, as a flowchart, a very general model of the deferred acceptance procedure, consistent with the APPIC rules. It may have random elements, and they may involve arbitrary probability distributions. There may be an arbitrary termination time t* (beyond which the acceptance of offers may not automatically be deferred), or no fixed termination time at all (if t* = infinity), in which case the deferred acceptance procedure continues until no firm wishes to make any more offers. If there is a fixed termination time, there may be an aftermarket (as in the psychology market), or none. And, reflecting the fact that we may not be able to observe the preferences in the market, these too may be regarded as random variables.

Box 0 of the flowchart begins the process with all positions vacant and all workers unmatched. The (random) preferences of the agents, chosen here, are fixed throughout the remainder of the process.

Box 1 models the deferred acceptance procedure, by telephone, in which a random element is introduced by the fact that only one firm may speak to a worker at a time. The possible reasons for termination are modeled in boxes 2a and b--either because all offers have been exhausted (2a), or because time has run out (2b). Note that the centralized deferred acceptance algorithm terminates only when all offers are exhausted, so it would be modeled here with a termination time t* = infinity in (2b). If the psychology market terminates because all offers are exhausted, then there is no need for an aftermarket. However, if the deferred acceptance part of the psychology market terminates because time has run out, then the aftermarket opens, in which acceptances can no longer be deferred, because offers are now exploding. Here too the telephone network introduces a random element, precisely as in box 1.

For comparison purposes only, it will be convenient to consider also an artificial market in which there is a termination time but no aftermarket (indicated by the dotted line from step 2b).

We will use the model given in Figure 1 to compare centralized and decentralized matching, and to consider the effects of changing the length of the market. It will help clarify matters to consider first how to compare the preferences agents submit in the centralized procedure with the choices we might observe them make in the decentralized procedure. A firm which makes offers to several workers in the decentralized procedure can be said to prefer them in the order in which the offers are made, and a worker who rejects an offer while holding another can be said to prefer the offer held. However, this will typically yield only a partial order, for two reasons. First, the procedure will typically terminate before full preference lists are revealed. Second, if for example, a worker holds an offer from firm F while rejecting one from F', and then receives and rejects an offer from F" while continuing to hold F, this "reveals" an ordering in which F is preferred to both F' and F", but gives no information about comparisons between F' and F". Thus there may be more than one preference relation consistent with the revealed preferences for each such agent 15. But it is not hard to see that the outcome of the deferred acceptance procedure is insensitive to those parts of the preferences which are not revealed, i.e. that the outcome is the same for any preferences consistent with those which are partially revealed by the decentralized procedure. In addition, if there is no fixed termination time, we can state the following theorem. (Note that the revealed preferences are always strict, whether or not the underlying preferences are.)

Theorem 1: If the decentralized deferred acceptance procedure is run without any fixed termination time (i.e. t* = infinity), then the outcome would be the same stable matching as that produced by the centralized deferred acceptance procedure. In particular, both procedures produce the firm-optimal stable matching with respect to the revealed preferences, muF.

Sketch of the Proof: We need to show that the outcome of the decentralized procedure is not influenced by the random elements of step 1a, but is always a fixed matching (as a function of the realized preferences). (When t = infinity the random elements of the aftermarket (step 3a) are never reached.) Then we have to show that this fixed matching is always the firm optimal stable matching with respect to the revealed preferences. Both elements of the proof are almost immediate from the standard proof that the centralized deferred acceptance procedure (with no random elements) produces the matching �F. First, the outcome of the decentralized procedure is stable with respect to the realized preferences, because (regardless of the order in which firms have made offers) there can be no blocking pairs for the final matching because if a firm prefers some worker to one of its matched employees, it must have already proposed to that worker and been rejected. Second, no firm is ever rejected by a worker to whom it could be matched at some stable matching. (This follows in the standard way by induction, see e.g. Roth and Sotomayor 1990, page 33.) Thus the final matching is always the firm optimal stable matching, and so the outcome is independent of the random elements in step 1a. Q.E.D.

Describing the outcome in terms of the revealed preferences raises the question of whether the agents have incentives to behave strategically in ways that make their revealed preferences different from their true preferences (i.e. from the preferences they would use to choose an outcome if they could do so as a single person decision rather than through a complex strategic interaction). The deferred acceptance algorithm has received a good deal of study from this point of view (cf. Roth and Sotomayor 1990). The simplest case to summarize is the one in which each firm seeks only one worker. In this case it is a dominant strategy for firms, but not for workers, to reveal their true preferences; yet all equilibria in undominated strategies produce outcomes that are stable with respect to the true preferences (even though workers may not have revealed these). But as we will see, a fixed time limit in the decentralized procedure (as in the APPIC rules), gives agents on both sides of the market reasons to behave strategically. The remaining theorems of this section, which are stated in terms of straightforward (truthful preference revealing) play, will set the stage for this observation by showing that straightforward play has different consequences for different termination times.

In the markets modeled by the flowchart in Figure 1, when there is a finite termination time, the random elements matter, and we get random matchings, which depend on the termination time. It will be easiest to understand this by considering first a hypothetical market run without an aftermarket.

Theorem 2: For markets in which there is no aftermarket, let tau < sigma < infinity, and let mutau, musigma, and muinfinity be the random matchings which result from straightforward play in otherwise identical decentralized deferred acceptance procedures having termination times tau, sigma, and infinity, respectively. For any worker w with realized preferences Pw, muinfinity(w) >>w musigma(w) >>w mutau(w).

Proof: Because of the finiteness of the sets of firms and workers there are only finitely many sample paths which can be realized even in the procedure with t* = infinity. (Every sample path will terminate in finite time.) Because the three procedures which give rise to the random matchings mutau, musigma, and muinfinity are identical except for their termination times, we can consider each sample path which has a positive probability of occurring in the t* = infinity procedure, and observe that the part of this path which is realized up to time tau has equal chance of occurring in the procedures with t* = tau, sigma, and infinity. Similarly, the part of this path which is realized up to time sigma has equal chance of occurring in the procedures with t* = sigma and infinity. On such a path the set of offers that have been made to each worker, and rejected or held, is the same up to time tau in all three procedures, and up to time sigma in the t* = sigma and t* = infinity procedures. To put it another way, in comparing two random procedures which are identical before the termination time of one of them, each sample path of the shorter procedure corresponds to a family of sample paths of the longer procedure which are all identical up to the earlier termination time.

Consider now a worker w in the t* = tau procedure. If the sample path we are considering terminates before time tau, then w receives the same match in procedures with t* [greater than or equal to] tau, and so in what follows we are free to concentrate on those sample paths in which the procedure terminates at tau due to lack of time (i.e. terminates due to rule 2b in the flowchart of Figure 1). If w is holding an offer from firm Fi at time tau, then mutau(w) = Fi, while the probabilities Pr{musigma(w) [is greater than or equal to]w Fi} = Pr{muinfinity(w) [is greater than or equal to]w Fi} = 1, because in the procedures which continue after time tau worker w holds the offer from Fi to the end unless she receives a preferable offer. And if w is holding no offer at time tau, then because there is no aftermarket w is unmatched, i.e. mutau(w) = w, and so it follows trivially that Pr{musigma(w) [is greater than or equal to]w w} = Pr{musigma(w) [is greater than or equal to]w w} = 1. We can compare musigma(w) and muinfinity(w) in the same way. Since muinfinity(w) [is greater than or equal to]w musigma(w) [is greater than or equal to]w mutau(w) on each sample path, it follows that muinfinity(w) >>w musigma(w) >>w mutau(w). Q.E.D.

We note with the following counterexample, however, that the comparison between the market with t* = infinity and the psychology market is not so simple.

Counterexample: For a market with an aftermarket, it is not the case that if tau < sigma, then musigma(w) >>w mutau(w).

Proof: Let F = {F1, F2}, W = {w1, w2} and the joint distribution of preferences be such that the two firms always have the preference w1 >F w2 for F in F, and the two workers always have the same preferences; either F1 >w F2 for each w in W, or the reverse. Then at the firm optimal stable matching w1 is matched to the most preferred firm; so this is the outcome in the deferred acceptance process with t* = infinity. Now consider t* = tau < infinity with tau small enough so there is time for only one offer to reach w1, so there is a positive probability that w1 will have received only an offer from the less preferred firm at time tau, i.e. a positive probability that mutau(w1) is the less preferred firm while mutau(w2) is the more preferred firm. Then muinfinity does not stochastically dominate mutau from w2's point of view. Q.E.D.

Although the counterexample shows that Theorem 2 will not apply directly to the comparison between the centralized and decentralized markets, the following theorem shows that a conditional version applies. To state the next theorem, define w(t) to be the number of acceptable offers worker w has received up to time t in a given run of the decentralized procedure.

Theorem 3: Conditional on having received at least one acceptable offer by time tau, the distribution of muinfinity(w) stochastically dominates that of musigma(w), which in turn stochastically dominates that of mutau(w) for tau < sigma < infinity. That is, for every v in F [union] {w},

Pr{muinfinity(w) >w v | w(tau) [does not equal] 0} [is greater than or equal to] Pr{musigma(w) >w v | w(tau) [does not equal] 0} [is greater than or equal to] Pr{mutau(w) >w v | w(tau) [does not equal] 0}.

Proof: The counterexample shows that the part of the proof of Theorem 2 which does not go through when there is an aftermarket is the case in which w is holding no offer at time tau. But conditional on having received an offer by time tau, worker w will be holding an offer from some firm Fi at time tau, and the proof of Theorem 2 for that case constitutes the proof of Theorem 3. Q.E.D

There are no welfare comparisons for firms similar to those for workers given by Theorems 2 and 3 (in particular the opposite stochastic dominance relations do not hold for firms) because it can always happen that an offer is rejected just before the termination time, so the firm has an empty position when the deferred acceptance part of the market ends. If, instead of terminating at that moment, the market were to continue, such a firm could do better than if the market stops completely. But firms not in this situation always do better with shorter termination times. To state this formally, define F(t) to be the number of workers holding offers from firm F at time t.

Theorem 4: Let tau < sigma < infinity, and let mutau, musigma, and muinfinity be the corresponding random matchings resulting from straightforward play. Then conditional on having all of its positions held at time tau, the distribution of mutau(F) stochastically dominates that of musigma(F) which stochastically dominates that of muinfinity(F), from the point of view of a firm F with realized preferences (over individuals) P(F), and responsive preferences over groups of workers. That is, for any feasible assignment of workers mu(F),

Pr{mutau(F) >F mu(F) | F(tau) = qF} [greater than or equal to] Pr{musigma(F) >F mu(F) | F(tau) = qF} [greater than or equal to] Pr{muinfinity(F) >F mu(F) | F(tau) = qF}.

The essential element of the proof, after which the argument is the same as for Theorems 2 and 3, is that on any sample path, since F has responsive preferences (and since F(tau) = qF) firm F prefers mutau(F) to any set of workers which hold its offers at some later time t > tau. Q.E.D.

Theorem 4 is much more delicate than Theorem 3. The comparison in Theorem 3 is for workers who have received at least one offer by time tau, but Theorem 4 concerns firms which have all their offers held at time tau, a status which could evaporate at any instant, if the market were to continue.

Note also that Theorems 3 and 4 present comparisons between the distributions of the matchings resulting from markets with different termination times, but do not tell us anything about the magnitudes of these comparisons. If the transaction times are so fast so that the market terminates due to all offers being exhausted before the deadline tau, then Theorem 1 tells us that the distributions compared in Theorems 3 and 4 will in fact be equal. And if, instead, the market deadline was very short compared to the number of transactions required even to get offers to most workers, then the events on which the probability comparisons in the two theorems are conditioned would rarely occur.

To put it another way, Theorems 3 and 4 could have been stated in terms of changes in the time needed to accept and reject offers, rather than changes in the total time available for the deferred acceptance part of the market. What matters is the effective length of the market--i.e. how many of the transactions needed for the market to fully clear can in fact be completed before the termination time. Simulations will allow us to see that with communication times like those observed in the psychology market, the market will generally not terminate before time runs out, but most workers will have received an offer and most firms will have all of their positions held, when the deferred acceptance part of the market ends. Therefore the unconditional distributions will have essentially the same relationship as the conditional distributions described in the Theorems.

B. Some market simulations with uncorrelated preferences:

Both the psychology and medical markets contain partially overlapping specialized submarkets of different sizes (cf Roth and Xing, 1994). To cleanly compare the effect of the different procedures used in these markets, we begin by considering a representative "generic" market or submarket consisting of two hundred potential employees and fifty employers, each with four positions to fill. Each worker has preferences over 20 randomly selected employers, such that he is equally likely to prefer the employers in any order. Each employer has preferences over all the workers who apply to it (i.e. over all workers such that the employer is included in the worker's preferences), and each employer is equally likely to prefer the workers who have applied to it in any order 16. (For later comparisons we'll also consider the case in which all workers have preferences over all firms, and vice versa.)

Actions in the simulation occur each minute. Each employer has two phones, one for outgoing and one for incoming calls. (The site we discussed earlier had two phones for outgoing calls and one for incoming calls, but we will see that our results are sensitive to the number of phones only in the opening hours of the market--which constitute its parallel processing phase--and this sharply limits the maximum potential effect of increasing the number of phones.) Students are modeled as having one telephone, used for both incoming and outgoing calls. Except when specifically indicated otherwise, calls initiated by employers for the purpose of making offers last 5 minutes, and all other calls last 1 minute.

In what follows we report the results of a number of simulated markets, which differ both in their rules for termination and in the assumptions we make about the behavior of participants on both sides of the market. It will be simplest to describe all of these results by first considering the simplest model, of the deferred acceptance procedure conducted by telephone, in which the market terminates only when all transactions are completed, and in which employers and students decide which offers to make, accept, hold, and reject by straightforwardly consulting their preferences without delay. As indicated above, the outcome of the market in such a case will correspond to the outcome using the centralized deferred acceptance algorithm with the same preferences. For this reason we refer to this model as the medical model (although keep in mind that the modern American medical market has complications which require significant modifications of the algorithm, and change the properties of its outcome--see Roth 1995, 1996). By following the timing of events in this deferred acceptance algorithm conducted by telephone, we will provide a basis of comparison for the psychology market, with its fixed termination time.

1. The simulated medical model telephone market:

The simulation of the medical model is as follows. When the market opens, each employer places a call to its top ranked candidate. (When multiple employers place simultaneous calls to the same student, one selected at random is connected, while the others receive busy signals). A phone conversation initiated by an employer to convey an offer takes 5 minutes to complete (so the phone is busy for 5 minutes). If the call is from the student's first choice employer (or from his first choice remaining employer after more preferred employers have called to inform the student that all their positions have been filled--see below) then the student accepts the offer in the course of the phone call. If the student has already received an offer from a preferred employer (whether this offer has already been accepted or is being held) then the student rejects the offer in the course of the phone call. Otherwise (i.e. if the offer is the best the student has so far received but there are more preferred employers which have not yet announced that all their positions are filled) the student "holds" the offer just received.

Employers who have just spoken to a candidate immediately call their next most preferred candidate if they have any positions remaining that have neither been accepted nor are being held. (Employers who have received a busy signal and who have only a single position available for which they have not already made an offer that is outstanding continue to try to place the call until it goes through. If they have more than one vacant position they call the other candidates for those positions before returning to the busy candidate.) If, following a phone call, all of an employer's positions have been accepted, the employer immediately calls all applicants with whom it has not yet communicated to inform them of this. (See rule 10a. These information calls take 1 minute.) If, following a call, an employer has some offers on hold (and no positions that have not either been accepted or held) then it waits, and initiates no further calls until it receives one from a student holding one of its offers.

Students who receive an offer from an employer which they prefer to an offer they are already holding hold the new offer (or accept it if it is from their first choice employer that hasn't yet announced that its positions are filled) and immediately call the employer whose offer they were already holding to reject that offer (rule 6a). If they have accepted the offer they also call all the employers on their preference list whose offers have not already been rejected to report that they have now taken an offer (rule 8). The employer whose offer was rejected immediately calls the highest ranked student on its preference list who has not previously rejected it or called to announce that another offer has been accepted, and conveys an offer to that student.

In the medical model there is no fixed termination time. Instead, the process terminates whenever no student is holding two offers and no employer still has an offer to make. The resulting outcome matches each student who has accepted an offer or is holding one when the process terminates to the corresponding employer.

a. Results of the medical model telephone simulations:

The medical model simulation is an implementation of the deferred acceptance procedure, and its outcome is the employer- optimal stable matching. The simulation allows us to observe how the offers are made over time. The first column of Table 1A shows the results of 100 simulations of this process, when, as described above, offers take 5 minutes and rejections take 1 minute.

The first thing to notice is that it is time consuming to run the deferred acceptance procedure by telephone--the mean time to achieve a stable outcome is over 18 hours (and the median time is over 16 hours). The time required in any particular simulation depends a great deal on the particular preferences, as shown by the fact that the standard deviation of these termination times is also high, at just over 8 hours. But even those simulations that are a full standard deviation faster than the mean require ten hours to produce a stable match. What is taking all this time?

The next entries in the first column of Table 1A indicate that the problem is not that it takes a long time to make initial contact with the bulk of the students. The average time required before 90% of the students have received at least one offer is barely more than one hour, and the average time before 99% of the students have at least one offer is less than five and a half hours. We are dealing with a population of 200 students per market, so when 99% of the students have received offers, only 2 students are still without an offer. In these simulations there are exactly as many students as positions, so the process terminates as soon as all 200 students have received offers. What can we make of the almost thirteen hours (18:18 - 5:19) that it apparently takes, on average, for the last two students to get offers?

To understand what is going on, we will examine directly the hourly progress of the market in terms of offers made, rejected, held etc. But note first that the rate-determining factor in these simulated markets is the turnaround time it takes for an offer to be rejected and a new offer to be made. To see this, look at the latter two columns of Table 1A. They report the same 100 simulations (i.e. begun with the same random preferences) as in column 1, but with a doubling and quintupling, respectively, of the turnaround times, which is achieved by doubling or quintupling both the time required to make an offer and the time required to reject an offer that is being held. The times for all other events-- information calls from students to employers or from employers to students, and the time needed to redial after busy signals--remain constant at 1 minute. So if the time required for information calls, for example, played an important role in determining the rate at which offers were made, the numbers in column 2 would be substantially less than twice those in column 1, and the numbers in column 3 would be substantially less than five times those in column 1. But this is not what we see--the figures in these two columns are very close to two and five times the column 1 figures. (And Table 1B shows that there are no important differences when students have preferences over all firms, and vice versa.)

Of course busy signals could still potentially play a large role, because when we increase the length of calls we increase the number and duration of busy signals. But it turns out that there is a strict limit on how much the market can be speeded up by reducing busy signals (e.g. by having all employers and students represented by staffs of telephonists at multiple phones). To see why, and to answer the questions raised above, we need to look at the simulations in more detail.

Looking first at the very last line of Table 2, we see that the longest of the one hundred simulations terminated by the 40th hour, at which point the average number of students who had received at least one offer was 199.99, reflecting that in one simulation only 199 students were matched at the employer-optimal stable matching, while in all the other simulations all 200 students were matched. The next column shows that, of course, by the time the markets had terminated every student had received an offer from the employer with whom he was ultimately matched. The next column shows that, on average, 882 offers were made to reach the stable outcome (i.e. 4.4 offers per position, or almost 18 offers per firm), and the final column shows that almost exactly half of these offers were rejected immediately, while half were held for at least some time.

Now looking at the top of Table 2 we see that 45% (400/882) of the average number of offers eventually made in 40 hours were in fact made in the first hour. Since each offer takes five minutes, this means that many offers were made in parallel. On average just over 178 distinct students received offers in the first hour, i.e. almost 90% (and recall from Table 1A that the 90% mark is actually reached at 1:02). But fewer than half of the students who received offers in the first hour (and at 86/200 only 43% of all students) had yet heard from the employer to whom they would ultimately be matched. So the market still has considerable work to do after the first hour.

However, the pace at which it accomplishes this work slows down dramatically. The reason is that, after the first hour, most firms have already offered all four of their positions to someone, and must wait for a rejection before they can make any new offers. So on average only 132 new offers (532-400) are made from hour 1 to hour 2, and these reach only 13 of the students who hadn't yet received any offer (191-178). And only 30 of these new offers reach students who will ultimately accept them (i.e. at the end of hour 2 only 116 students have received an offer from the employer to whom they would ultimately be matched). So there is still much further to go before the market clears.

The rate at which offers are made slows still further as the market progresses: on average only 70 offers (602-532) are made from hour 2 to hour 3, only 47 from hour 3 to hour 4 (649-602), and only 33 (682-649) from hour 4 to hour 5. By hour 5 almost 99% of the students have received at least one offer. But while only 1% of the students have yet to receive an offer at hour 5, 24% of the students ([200-152]/200) have yet to receive an offer from the employer with whom they will be matched when the market clears and a stable matching has been reached.

Recall that when 99% of the students in these particular markets have received an offer, at most 2 students can be holding more than one offer. So (at a moment when this is the case) there will be only 2 calls being placed, after which at most 2 firms will have vacancies, so only two more calls will be placed, etc. And when 99.5% of the students have received offers (which happens on average after hour 8) there will only be one phone call going at a time. Only between 10 and 12 new offers can be made per hour at this point (since offers that are rejected immediately have a turnaround time of 5 minutes, while an offer that causes another offer to be rejected causes a new offer to be completed only after 6 minutes). But after hour 8 there remain on average 137 offers (882-745) to be made before the market clears 17. Thus the bulk of the time before the market ends is spent when offers must be made serially.

By the end of hour 7, the time at which the psychology market closes, on average fewer than 2% of the students in the medical model simulations are without offers. But 16% of the students have yet to receive the offers they would finally accept. We turn next to consider the consequence of terminating the market at this point. We begin with a simulation in which all agents continue to consult their preferences straightforwardly and without delay.

2. The simulated psychology market with straightforward behavior

These simulations of the psychology market follow exactly the rules of the previous simulations, up until the end of hour 7. At that point, all offers which are still being held are accepted (by default, which takes no time), and any firm which has not filled one of its positions continues to call the candidates remaining on its list of preferences, until an unmatched candidate accepts the offer, or until it runs out of candidates to call. Any unmatched candidate accepts the first offer he receives 18.

The first column of Table 3 gives the results of these simulations. Naturally, the times at which 90% and 99% of the students have received at least one offer are like those in the previous simulations, and well before the hour 7 deadline. But, since all outstanding offers are accepted after the deadline is reached, the resulting matching of students to programs need not be stable. Typically there will be blocking pairs, i.e. a student and an internship program who are not matched to one another but who each ranked one another higher than the outcome they received at the end of the market.

The first column of Table 3 shows that at the end of these markets (i.e. after all calls following the expiration of the deadline have been completed), on average almost 2 firms and 17 workers can take part in such blocking pairs, i.e. about 4% of the firms and 8% of the workers. Now, at the moment that the deadline expires, any firm who can be part of a blocking pair must have at least one position unfilled 19. So these firms immediately start calling the workers who have not yet rejected them, and, since 8% of the workers can take part in blocking pairs, it is not at all a rare event that a firm finds itself talking to a worker with whom it could form a blocking pair. The vast majority of such workers have already accepted an offer from another firm (since on average fewer than 1% of the workers received no offer by the deadline, so more than 99% have accepted offers). This is the origin of the incentives to break the rules, in each of the ways so carefully enumerated in parts a through e of rule 7.

The incentives to break the rules live on beyond the end of the telephone calls which follow the expiration of the deadline. Firms and workers who were unmatched at the deadline, and especially those who remain unmatched when all remaining transactions have been exhausted, have been badly hurt by the fact that there is a deadline (i.e. in comparison to the outcome they could have expected if the market were conducted as in the medical market). Even if these dissatisfied individuals and firms are fully bound by their verbal commitments, firms have an incentive (the following year) to try to avoid the risk of being caught short at the deadline, by breaking the rules against early offers, or against pressuring students into revealing their preferences so that offers can be concentrated on students who will accept promptly.

And students, who also face the risk of being caught short at the deadline, may be willing to go along with the attempt to arrange early matches, or to signal their preferences in order to attract prompt offers. Indeed, the first column of Table 4, which shows the hourly progress of offers in this market, shows that any student who doesn't get an offer in the first hour has a substantial (9%) risk of getting no offer by the deadline. So there is reason for students to worry about what will happen to them if they don't get an offer in the early, parallel processing phase of the market.

Note also, by comparing the hourly transactions in this market with those in the market with no deadline (Tables 2 and 4), that there are on average almost 100 fewer offers made when the market has a 7 hour deadline. That is, although there is only a small difference between the two markets in terms of how many positions are filled, there is a substantial difference in terms of how many potential transactions are evaluated to determine which individuals will fill which positions. Thus the instability of the final outcome, and the incentives for firms to identify workers who will accept immediately, arise from the fact that this market closes before it clears.

We turn next to briefly consider the effects when some firms and workers act on these incentives.

3. The simulated psychology market in which employers seek out those who will accept their offers immediately

These simulations follow exactly the rules of the previous psychology market simulations, except that instead of making offers strictly in order of preference, each firm makes its first offers to any students among its 10 most preferred students for whom that firm is the first choice. (This can be interpreted as the case in which every student identifies himself to his first choice firm, and in which each firm acts on this information only if the students who identify themselves are among its top choices 20.)

The aggregate results of these simulations are presented in column 5 of Table 3. The difference between these simulations and those of the psychology market with straightforward behavior are quite modest, both because only a minority of firms change their behavior (and even then only in regard to their initial offers), and because this change of behavior slows down some transactions at the same time that it speeds up others. That is, even though certain students who have indicated that they would immediately accept an offer receive one sooner than if firms acted straightforwardly on their preferences, other students receive offers later than they would have, and not merely because the firms have changed the order of their offers. The parallel processing phase of the market more quickly gives way to the serial phase, since some firms have one of their positions accepted faster, and thus can't do as much parallel processing of offers. Thus in these simulations the mean time at which 90% of students have received offers comes 5 minutes sooner than when behavior is straightforward, but it takes 16 minutes longer before 99% of the students have received offers.

This kind of behavior yields more firms which can take part in blocking pairs with respect to the final outcome. This reflects that a firm which makes an offer to, say, its 9th ranked candidate because that candidate happens to rank it first, may be missing a chance to hire its 4th or 5th ranked candidate. But as we have seen, firms may be prepared to pay this cost to avoid the risk of being caught with a vacant position when the market closes.

We will return to this when we consider the differential welfare effects of these different market rules and behaviors. But first we consider the effect on the market when some students may delay before rejecting some offers, i.e. when they may sometimes hold more than one offer.

4. Simulated psychology markets in which some students may sometimes hold two offers

There have been persistent complaints that students may sometimes hold more than one offer, i.e. that they may delay in rejecting offers (see e.g. Belar and Orgel, 1980). Rule 6 is now specifically meant to prevent this. Here we investigate the consequences of such delays.

Where the previous section investigated behavior which agents might exhibit in response to the incentives they face in the market, the behavior we study here is maladaptive. In the deferred acceptance procedure, students can only do better as they receive more offers. So a student who slows the market by holding multiple offers can only reduce the number of offers he will get by the time the market closes. This does not mean, of course, that there are not reasons that students might hold multiple offers, having to do either with mistakes, or with (hard to model but real) costs of decision making 21. Delayed decision making might take different forms, depending on its causes. We therefore model delays in two ways.

In the first set of simulations, 10% of the students are randomly selected as being potential delayers, and the first time any one of these students receives an offer when she is already holding one (i.e. when she receives her second offer), she delays responding for two hours (or until the deadline, whichever comes first), and thereafter reverts to straightforward behavior without any further delays. The delays in these simulations can be thought of as arising from simple mistakes or carelessness 22.

In the second and third set of simulations, every student has the potential to have a delay, which occurs the first time she finds herself holding two adjacent offers neither of which is her first choice. The idea is that if she's holding e.g. her 3rd and 4th choice offers, then a delay offers the possibility that she'll get an offer from her (clear) first choice, and not have to decide 23. In the second set of simulations we suppose that (perhaps out of fear that rule 6b may be activated) students end their delay an hour before the deadline, after which they reject the less preferred of the offers and continue in a straightforward manner with no further delays. In the third set of simulations we suppose that the delay continues all the way to the deadline at the end of hour 7, at which point the student accepts the more preferred offer and rejects the other, and the simulation of the aftermarket proceeds straightforwardly 24.

Table 3 shows the results of these simulations, and allows comparison with the psychology market simulations with no delays. In all these markets, the 7 hour deadline means that all transactions remaining after the deadline are quickly concluded, so there is not too much difference in mean times to termination. Similarly, the fact that the initial part of the market can process offers in parallel means that the time by which 90% of the students have received offers is delayed by much less than the length of each individual's delay (e.g. in the market with two hour delays, the 90% mark comes only 69 minutes after the market with no delays). The story is different with the 99% mark, which in each of the markets with delays now comes after the deadline for the deferred acceptance part of the market, so that many more students are faced with exploding offers in the aftermarket than in the market with no delays. (In 100 simulations of the market in which students may hold adjacent offers until the deadline, not a single offer was made between hours 4 and 7, and very few offers were made after hour 2. 25. And there is an enormous difference in the stability of the final outcome, compared to the market with no delays. In the market with the longest delays, a quarter of the firms and 40% of the workers can be involved in blocking pairs with respect to the final outcome. So in the markets with delays, the incentives for breaking the rules have risen enormously.

5. Welfare comparisons among different rules and behaviors

Table 5 allows us to compare the welfare effects of the different regimes we have considered. For the simulations of each model (of the rules of the market and the behavior of the participants) it shows how many students are matched with their first choice firm, their second choice, etc. Dividing these numbers by 200 yields the probability that a random student would have ended up in each position on his preference list, including the possibility of being unmatched.

We will defer for a moment the case when firms don't behave straightforwardly, and concentrate first on the comparisons among the other five models. Here the comparisons are striking and unambiguous, as we can order these five models (as in the Table) so that the distribution of outcomes for each one stochastically dominates the distribution for the next. That is, the students do best under the medical model (with no termination time), next best under the psychology model with straightforward behavior, and increasingly worse as the length of the delay during which two offers may be held increases. For example, a student has a higher probability of getting each of his first four choices when there is no termination time (the medical model) than when there is (the psychology model), and a lower probability of getting each of his choices 5 through 20 or of being unmatched.

The reason is that, in the deferred acceptance procedure, a worker can only be helped by getting an additional offer, so workers' success in the market is monotonic in the number of offers they receive. Introducing a deadline, or increasing the length of delays, all act to reduce the expected number of offers a worker will receive. That is, these simulations show that the conclusions of Theorem 3 apply. As we have already noted in Table 3, the events on which the conclusions of Theorem 3 are conditioned (that any particular student has received at least one offer by the deadline) are highly probable, and the inequalities in the conclusion of Theorem 3 are likely to be strict, since the effective length of these markets, as measured by the number of offers for which there is time, are strictly different.

As in Theorem 4, it is more complicated to evaluate the welfare of the firms, primarily because, in contrast to the workers, the decreasing number of offers made and the increasing chance of having a position unfilled work in opposite directions for the firms. We can separate out the two effects by considering the expected success of a firm in each of the five models, conditional on the firm filling all of its positions. In this case, the welfare of the firms is ordered in exactly the opposite order of the welfare of the workers. (For example, to choose a simple measure, the probability that a firm will fill its four positions with its first four choices is lowest in the medical model, higher in the psychology model with straightforward behavior, and higher still in the models with increasing delays. 26.) This is so even though the medical model produces the firm-optimal stable outcome; the other markets produce unstable outcomes that are better for those firms which have all their positions filled.

Of course, the very worst thing that can happen to a firm is that one or more of its offers should be rejected just before the deadline, so it doesn't have time to get new offers out before all workers accept the offers they are holding. When the market rules are followed, this means that such a firm must either remain unmatched, or find a match with a worker who did not receive any offers before the deadline. If this is a sufficiently undesirable outcome (as it seems to be to many market participants we have spoken to), the increasing risk of remaining unmatched may even cause firms' preferences to coincide with workers' preferences over these five market regimes 27. Another factor working in this direction is that increased instability of the final market outcome presumably causes more violations of the rules, and insofar as the firms have a long term interest in the orderly operation of the market, they may prefer those regimes which offer rule-breaking incentives to the fewest potential blocking pairs.

As already noted, comparing these five models to the remaining model, in which the firms don't act straightforwardly on their preferences, is more nuanced, because the firms' actions cut different ways in the parallel and serial phases of the market. Table 5 shows that the distribution of students over the choices they match to in this model neither stochastically dominates nor is dominated by the distribution from the psychological model with straightforward behavior. The distribution is stochastically dominated by the distribution of the medical model (without a termination time), and it dominates the distributions in the three models with delays. This simply confirms the large effects which introducing a deadline, and experiencing delays, have on reducing the number of offers in the market (and therefore reducing the welfare of the workers).

C. Sensitivity to the joint distribution of preferences, and to the concentration of positions: 1. Correlated preferences

So far we have reported simulations in which all preferences are uncorrelated. Now we consider the robustness of the results when preferences are correlated, reflecting some agreement on which are the most desirable firms and workers. The chief result is that increasing the correlation among firms' preferences makes it even more difficult for the market to clear, because the initial phase of the market becomes more congested, with many firms lining up to make offers to the most preferred workers. The simplest way to see this is to begin with the extreme cases when preferences are either identical or completely independent. Varying this separately for the workers (students) and for the firms yields four cases, shown in Table 6. (In order to allow preferences on each side of the market to be identical, each student has preferences over all firms, and vice versa, so Table 6 is comparable to Table 1B.)

Case 1 in Table 6 shows the results for both the medical and psychology markets in the case we have already considered, in which all preferences are uncorrelated. (The medical market numbers in case 1 reproduce those in column 1 of Table 1B.) Comparing the medical markets in case 1 and case 2 of Table 6 shows that the change from uncorrelated to common preferences among the firms dramatically slows the critical early hours of the market (although the mean time to termination is only modestly longer in case 2 than in case 1.) The mean time by which 90% of the students have received at least one offer goes from just over 1 hour in the medical market when firms have uncorrelated preferences, to just over 22 hours when they have identical preferences. Because firms' preferences are perfectly correlated in case 2, they all attempt to make their first offers to the same students, and in the resulting congestion an average of only 11 students (5.5%) receive at least one offer in the first hour.

To put it another way, by the time the 7 hours available in the psychology market has expired, 99% of the students have received at least one offer when the firms have uncorrelated preferences (in case 1), but only 31% have when the firms' preferences are perfectly correlated (case 2). So in the psychology market, the exploding offer aftermarket makes most of the matches in case 2, in contrast to case 1, as can be seen by comparing the mean numbers of firms and students which can participate in blocking pairs to destabilize the final outcome in the two cases. When the firms' preferences are uncorrelated, on average only 2 firms and 31 students can participate in blocking pairs. But when firms' preferences are perfectly correlated (and most matching is done by the aftermarket), an average of 48 firms and 151 students can participate in destabilizing blocking pairs.

Comparing cases 4 and 3 shows that going from uncorrelated to perfectly correlated firms' preferences has the same effect whether students' preferences are correlated or uncorrelated.

Correlation of students' preferences, in contrast, speeds up the serial part of the market. This is clearest comparing cases 1 and 4 in Table 6, i.e comparing the effect of correlation of students' preferences when firms' preferences are uncorrelated. In both cases 1 and 4, the first hour of the market has a big parallel processing component. Both when students' preferences are uncorrelated and when they are perfectly correlated, it takes a little over an hour for 90% of the students to receive their first offer, and in both cases the mean time by which 99% of the students have received at least one offer is under 8 hours. But when students' preferences are perfectly correlated, much more sorting of firms takes place in the early hours of the market. (For example, in case 1 at the end of hour 7 the mean number of students who have received at least one offer is 197.59, and in case 4 the number is 196.87, virtually identical. But in case 1, in which students' preferences are uncorrelated, the mean number of students who have by this time received an offer from the firm to which they will ultimately be matched in the medical market is only 155.4, while in case 4 this number is 196.15.) So the final, serial part of the market moves much faster when students' preferences are correlated, because fewer offers need to be made before a stable matching is achieved 28. This is reflected in the much longer mean (and median) times to termination in the case 1 than case 4 medical markets, and in the larger number of potential blocking pairs in the case 1 than case 4 psychology markets 29.

Note that the case in which both students and firms have perfectly correlated preferences is a good example in which the assumptions and conclusions of Theorem 3 do not hold. Because the firms all have common preferences, we can identify, for example, the least desirable student, who is matched at the unique stable matching (and hence at the outcome of the medical market) to the least desirable firm (which is also well defined since students have identical preferences). Because of the congestion caused by the correlation of the firms' preferences in this market, this least desirable student is virtually certain to be unmatched at the end of hour 7, which means that in the psychology market he is matched during the exploding offer aftermarket. This introduces a large random component, so this student's distribution of possible matches is better in the short (psychology) market, than in the longer medical market.

In summary, the more highly correlated with one another are the firms' preferences, the more congestion there is at the beginning of the market, so the longer it takes for workers to receive offers. When the deferred acceptance part of the market has a 7 hour termination time, this means that the number of instabilities increases as firms' preferences become more highly correlated. In contrast, more highly correlated workers' preferences speed the sorting of firms and shorten the length of the market, and reduce the number of instabilities. But there are substantial bottlenecks even in the best case (when firms' preferences are uncorrelated and workers' preferences are identical). And when both firms and workers have highly correlated preferences, the congestion due to the firms' preferences predominates, because it slows down the rate at which workers receive offers (and because a worker's preferences do not begin to have any effect until she receives at least two offers).

2. Concentration of positions:

So far we have reported simulations in which the 200 positions are always offered by 50 firms. To see the effect of concentration, we consider a range of markets, starting with much more concentrated markets (2 firms each with 100 positions), and ending with less concentrated markets (200 firms each with one position). Of course, if we continued to model each firm as having only one telephone for outgoing calls, we would introduce an arbitrary kind of serial processing in the most concentrated markets. To make these comparisons informative about the transition between parallel and serial processing, we therefore relax any constraint on the number of simultaneous offers a given firm can make. (This would be natural, for example, in a market in which offers were made by mail.) This is equivalent to modeling each firm as having "infinitely many" phones; i.e. a large enough staff of telephonists to offer all of its positions simultaneously. Having no constraint on the number of simultaneous offers a firm can make speeds up the parallel processing part of the market (so the times for the next simulations are not comparable to those reported above). But having many phones doesn't speed the market at all when most firms must wait for an offer to be rejected before they can issue a new one.

Table 7 reports the results as we vary the number n of firms; n = 2, 5, 10, 20, 50, 100, 200. In each market, all firms and students have uncorrelated random preferences. Each firm has infinitely many phones, while each student has only one phone. The number of students and the number of total positions are constant at 200; each firm in the market has 200/n positions to fill.

The simulations show that the mean time to termination increases with the number of firms, as do the times by which 90% and 99% of the students are matched. For each concentration of positions, the substantial differences between each of these three times shows that there is a clear transition between the early, parallel processing part of the market in which the bulk of the students receive at least one offer, and the later, much more extended serial processing part of the market.

III. Concluding remarks

Even the extremely short turnaround times characteristic of the entry level market for clinical psychologists can cause bottlenecks, which impede market clearing and promote strategic behavior. This is robust to changes in the correlation of preferences and in the concentration of positions, and seems likely to have implications not only for other labor markets, but for markets generally.

The turnaround time makes itself felt when the market enters a phase in which most potential transactions must be processed serially. It is useful to distinguish between congestion-based serial processing, and serial processing which arises because of the nature of the transactions.

It appears that any market can be forced by congestion into serial processing. Even in stock exchanges, which have perhaps the highest degree of parallel processing of proposed transactions (in the sense that every bid or asked price can be offered to the whole market), great congestion may cause serial processing (e.g. in the specialist's book) which may contribute to market "meltdowns." But if the market and specialist firms hired more staff, more transactions could be processed simultaneously.

The serial processing we have been considering arises in a more fundamental way. It arises even in markets in which firms have no communications constraints, and can offer all of their available positions simultaneously. The bottlenecks arise not from a lack of processing capacity, but from the fact that, after most workers have received at least one offer, most firms must wait for an offer to be rejected before they can issue a new offer, and this takes time. It seems likely that any market in which agents propose transactions by making offers which must be left open for at least a short specified period has the potential to experience this phase transition 30.

The turnaround time itself doesn't cause markets to end prematurely, but must be considered along with the duration of the market to determine the market's effective length, which (for a labor market) we can roughly define as the average number of sequential offers which a firm can expect to have time to make for a given position 31. In markets in which salaries (and other dimensions of the job) are negotiated, there is more reason for workers to hold multiple offers (which may be used for leverage in negotiation), and the resulting delays in rejecting offers will decrease the effective length of the market.

It is not simple to extend the effective length of a market. For example, in previous years the psychology market had a longer duration. But the short turnaround time in the current market is related to its seven hour duration, which allows everyone to plan to spend the day next to the telephone. In a market conducted over five days, for example, people couldn't wait by the phone all the time, so turnaround time would likely go up by more than a factor of 5 (i.e. to more than 1/2 hour from the time someone decides to reject an offer until another candidate has received it). Thus this is a market in which extending the duration of the market might shorten its effective length.

Finally, we have discussed how there are particular incentives for strategic behavior in markets whose effective length is insufficient to guarantee market clearing. In the clinical psychology market these incentives lead to an emphasis on identifying candidates who will quickly accept an offer. In less centralized markets, firms with many different positions (e.g. universities which recruit in many departments) may make simultaneous multiple offers for each position. Similarly, firms have incentives to try to "capture" their top choices (and also to increase the effective length of their market) by making offers of very short duration, which shorten the effective length of the market faced by other firms by removing candidates from the market quickly. Thus a short effective length of a market can give agents incentives to behave in ways which further shorten the market's effective length. 32.

This in turn makes it increasingly difficult for the market to clear fully, and arrive at a stable outcome. And as was observed in Roth (1984, 1990, 1991), Mongell and Roth (1991) and Roth and Xing (1994), unstable outcomes can give agents the incentive to "jump the gun" and make very early offers, or try to disrupt agreements with late offers 33. Thus there is a relation between the turnaround times studied in this paper and the timing of early and late offers studied in those earlier papers. And even in markets which don't experience overt timing problems, firms have incentives to "target" the candidates to whom they will make their first offers, taking into account the probability that an offer will be accepted (i.e. not necessarily attempting to hire first the most preferred candidate). These strategic considerations make efficient outcomes more difficult to achieve 34.

Methodologically, this paper is part of a body of work which seeks to understand markets based on a detailed understanding of their rules, and how these have evolved over time. (If we wish game theory to become as integral a part of applied economics as it is of economic theory, it cannot be said too often that rules are data, and have to be collected and analyzed.) When we study naturally occurring games, instead of simple stylized models, it is to be expected that the size of the strategy space may preclude analysis by currently available theoretical tools. It is for this reason that we have relied here on computation, and have concentrated on straightforward behavior. The set of feasible strategies in the market studied here is too large to even sample sensibly, without some further understanding of the strategy space being sampled. Some thoughts on sampling strategy spaces and exploring them computationally are found in Erev and Roth (1996).

Substantively, this paper is part of a body of work which seeks to take seriously the role of time in markets. Considerations of timing play an important role in shaping the strategic environment facing market participants, and this in turn can have a profound influence on their behavior, and on the performance of the market.


Bibliography

Arenson, Karen W. [1996], "Top Colleges Fill More Slots With Those Applying Early," New York Times, CXLV, Wednesday February 14, 1, B8.

Becker, Edward R., Stephen G. Breyer, and Guido Calabresi [1994], "The Federal Judicial Law Clerk Hiring Problem and the Modest March 1 Solution," 104, Yale Law Journal, 207-225.

Belar, Cynthia D and Orgel, Sidney A. "Survival Guide for Intern Applicants," Professional Psychology, No. 4, August 1980, 11, 672- 675.

Blum, Yosef, Alvin E. Roth, and Uriel G. Rothblum "Vacancy Chains and Equilibration in Senior-Level Labor Markets," 1996, mimeo.

Bergstrom, Ted and Mark Bagnoli [1993], "Courtship as a Waiting Game," Journal of Political Economy, 101, 185-202.

Collins, Susan M. and Krishna, Kala, "The Harvard Housing Lottery: Rationality and Reform," working paper, The Brookings Institution, 1993.

Crawford, Vincent P., "Comparative Statics in Matching Markets," Journal of Economic Theory, 1991, 54, 389-400.

Erev, Ido and Roth, Alvin E., ""On the need for low rationality, cognitive game theory: Reinforcement learning in experimental games with unique, mixed strategy equilibria," mimeo.

Gale, David and Shapley, Lloyd, "College Admissions and the Stability of Marriage," American Mathematical Monthly, 1962, 69, 9- 15.

Li, Hao and Sherwin Rosen [1996], "Unraveling in Assignment Markets," mimeo, University of Chicago.

Mongell, Susan and Roth, Alvin E., "Sorority Rush as a Two-Sided Matching Mechanism," American Economic Review, 1991, 81, 441- 464.

Osborne, Martin J. and Ariel Rubinstein, Bargaining and Markets, San Diego, Academic Press, 1990.

Pollak, Robert A. [1994], ``For Better or Worse: The Roles of Power in Models of Distribution within Marriage,'' American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 84, May, 148-152.

Roth, Alvin E., "The Evolution of the Labor Market for Medical Interns and Residents: A Case Study in Game Theory", Journal of Political Economy, 1984, 92, 991-1016.

Roth, Alvin E. "The College Admissions Problem Is Not Equivalent to the Marriage Problem," Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 36, 1985, 277-288.

Roth, Alvin E., "On the Allocation of Residents to Rural Hospitals: A General Property of Two-Sided Matching Markets," Econometrica, 1986, 54, 425-427.

Roth, Alvin E., "New Physicians: A Natural Experiment in Market Organization," Science, 1990, 250, 1524-1528.

Roth, Alvin E., "A Natural Experiment in the Organization of Entry Level Labor Markets: Regional Markets for New Physicians and Surgeons in the U.K.", American Economic Review, 1991, 81, 415- 440.

Roth, A.E. "Evaluation of Changes to be Considered in the NRMP Algorithm," Consultant's report, 1995, mimeo and http://www.pitt.edu/~alroth/nrmp.html

Roth, A.E. "Interim Report #1: Evaluation of the current NRMP algorithm, and preliminary design of an applicant-proposing algorithm, March 1996, mimeo and http://www.pitt.edu/~alroth/nrmp.html

Roth, Alvin E. and Uriel G. Rothblum, "The Information Requirements of Strategic Behavior in Labor Markets and Other Matching Processes," in preparation (1995).

Roth, Alvin E. and Sotomayor, Marilda A. Oliveira, Two-Sided Matching: A Study in Game-Theoretic Modeling and Analysis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Roth, Alvin E. and Vande Vate, John H. "Random Paths to Stability in Two-Sided Matching," Econometrica, 58, 1990, 1475- 1480.

Roth, A.E. and Vande Vate, J.H. "Incentives in Two-Sided Matching with Random Stable Mechanisms," Economic Theory, 1991, vol. 1., no. 1, 31-44.

Roth, Alvin E. and Xiaolin Xing "Jumping the Gun: Imperfections and Institutions Related to the Timing of Market Transactions," American Economic Review, 1994, 84, 992-1044.

Rubinstein, Ariel "Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model," Econometrica, 50, 97-109.


Appendix
APPIC Policy: Internship Offers and Acceptances (Revised 5/91)

Adherence to these policies is a condition of membership in APPIC. (Rules 1 and 11-14 are omitted.)

2. Internship program directors must inform applicants who are excluded from consideration as early as possible in the process, and no later than one week before selection day.

  1. Students who remain under consideration may be notified that they remain under consideration after others have been excluded.
  2. No other information (such as agency's ranking of the applicant; status as alternate/first choice, etc.) may be communicated to applicants prior to selection day.

3. No internship offers in any form may be extended by agencies before the beginning of selection day.

  1. The only information that agencies may communicate to applicants prior to this time is whether or not the applicant remains under consideration for admission (see item 2). The spirit of this item precludes any communication of an applicant's status prior to the time above, however, "veiled" or indirect such communication might be.
  2. "Alternates" may be fully informed of their status any time after the start of selection day. Applicants may not be told whether they are considered alternates or first choices prior to that time.
  3. Internship programs may not solicit information regarding an applicant's ranking of programs or his/her intention to accept or decline an offer of admission until after that offer is officially tendered.

4. Applicants must reply to all offers no later than the closing time on selection day.

  1. This deadline applies to all offers including those to applicants who are initially considered "alternates" and are subsequently extended an offer any time prior to end of selection day.
  2. Agencies may inquire as to the applicant's progress towards making a decision at any time after an offer is formally extended. Under no circumstances, however, may an agency implicitly or explicitly threaten to rescind an offer if a decision is not made prior to the end of selection day (except as noted in item 6).
  3. It is in everyone's best interest that applicants make and communicate decisions to accept or reject each offer as quickly as possible.
  4. Any offer that has not been accepted is void as of the ending hour of selection day.

5. An applicant must respond immediately to each offer tendered in one of three ways. The offer may be accepted, rejected or "held."

  1. Accepting the offer constitutes a binding agreement between applicant and internship program.
  2. Refusing the offer terminates all obligations on either side and frees the internship program to offer the position to another applicant.
  3. Holding the offer means that the offer remains valid until the applicant notifies the program of rejection or acceptance, or until the end of selection day.

6. Applicants may "HOLD" no more than one active offer at a time.

  1. If an applicant is holding an offer from one program and receives an offer from a more preferred program, s/he may accept or "hold" the second offer provided that the less preferred program is notified immediately that the applicant is rejecting the previously held offer.
  2. If a program confirms that an applicant is holding more than one offer, the program is free to withdraw their previously tendered offer of acceptance, and to offer that position to another applicant after the offending applicant is notified of that decision.

7. An offer of acceptance to an applicant is valid only if the applicant has not already accepted an offer of admission to another program.

  1. An applicant's verbal acceptance of an offer constitutes a binding agreement between the applicant and the program that may not be reversed unilaterally by either party.
  2. Before programs extend an offer, they must first explicitly inquire whether the applicant has already accepted an offer elsewhere. If so, no offer may be tendered.
  3. A program may in no way suggest that an applicant renege on previously accepted offers.
  4. If an applicant who has accepted an offer receives a second offer, s/he is obligated to refuse the second offer and inform the agency that s/he is already committed elsewhere.
  5. Any offer accepted subsequently to a prior commitment is automatically null and void, even if the offering agency is unaware of the prior acceptance and commitment.

8. When an applicant accepts an offer of admission, s/he is urged to immediately inform all other internship programs at which s/he is still under consideration that s/he is no longer available.

9. Applicants who have not accepted a position prior to the end of selection day may receive offers of admission after that deadline.

  1. Applicants should be prepared to accept or reject such late offers quickly, since most other deliberations should have already taken place.
  2. Programs may legitimately place short but reasonable deadlines for responses to such late offers.

10. Once a program has filled all available positions, all candidates remaining in their applicant pool must be notified that they are no longer under consideration.

  1. Applicants who have not notified the agency that they have accepted a position elsewhere and who have not been selected by the agency should be notified by phone as soon as all positions are filled.
  2. If an applicant cannot be reached by phone, s/he should be so notified by letter postmarked no later than 72 hours after the end of selection day.



TABLE 1:
MEDICAL MODEL TELEPHONE MARKET; RESULTS OF 100 SIMULATIONS
FOR EACH OF THREE TURNAROUND TIMES
Number of Minutes Required To Make An Offer (& Reject One)
5 10 25
1 2 5
A. Preferences Over 20 Firms: Uncorrelated Random Preferences
Mean time to termination at a stable outcome 18:18 36:32 91:24
Standard Deviations 8:10 16:20 40:52
Median time to termination 16:24 32.39 81.19
Mean time by which 90% of students have received an offer 1:02 2:03 5:04
Mean time by which 99% of students have received an offer 5:19 10:35 26:22
Longest time to termination 39:25 78:25 196:22
Shortest time to termination 4:59 9:55 25:00
B. Preferences Over All 50 Firms: Uncorrelated Random Preferences
Mean time to termination at a stable outcome 22:53 45:35 113.42
Standard Deviations 12:03 24:04 60:12
Median time to termination 18:57 37:44 94:09
Mean time by which 90% of students have received an offer 1:09 2:15 5:35
Mean time by which 99% of students have received an offer 702 13:55 34:39
Longest time to termination 55:15 110:03 274:48
Shortest time to termination 6:10 12:12 30:50



TABLE 2:
HOURLY PROGRESS OF THE MEDICAL MODEL TELEPHONE MARKET
(100 Simulations)
Hour Number of Students with at Least One Offer Number of Students with an Offer from the Firm They Ultimately Match With Number of Offers Made Number of Offers Not Rejected Immediately
0 .00 .00 .00 .00
1 178.47 86.32 400.08 278.06
2 191.24 116.06 531.96 333.90
3 194.83 132.75 602.36 360.04
4 196.50 143.81 648.58 375.70
5 197.41 152.14 681.79 386.80
6 198.02 158.48 707.38 395.10
7 198.37 163.37 727.89 401.10
8 198.54 167.66 745.23 406.29
9 198.68 171.46 761.06 410.70
10 198.84 174.77 775.07 414.6 5
11 198.97 177.59 787.29 417.8 5
12 199.05 180.32 798.49 421.0 3
13 199.18 182.78 808.49 423.7 5
14 199.29 184.76 817.30 425.9 9
15 199.41 186.72 824.77 428.1 2
16 199.41 188.26 831.41 429.8 4
17 199.51 189.75 837.30 431.5 1
18 199.57 191.04 842.61 432.8 9
19 199.62 192.19 847.21 434.1 7
20 199.67 193.11 851.38 435.2 0
21 199.69 193.91 854.99 436.0 9
22 199.71 194.70 858.47 436.9 6
23 199.76 195.47 861.63 437.7 8
24 199.80 196.56 866.80 438.3 2
25 199.80 196.56 866.80 438.9 2
26 199.82 197.07 869.00 439.4 5
27 199.85 197.52 870.94 440.2 4
28 199.87 197.81 872.50 440.6 3
29 199.87 198.18 873.98 440.9 3
30 199.90 198.47 875.13 441.2 3
31 199.90 198.77 876.16 441.4 9
32 199.90 199.01 877.22 441.7 3
33 199.91 199.23 878.12 441.8 7
34 199.92 199.37 879.03 442.0 3
35 199.93 199.53 879.80 442.1 8
36 199.94 199.67 880.40 442.2 8
37 199.94 199.77 880.99 442.4 0
38 199.97 199.89 881.39 442.4 0
39 199.97 199.95 881.62 442.4 6
40 199.99 199.99 881.71 442.5 0



TABLE 3:
THE TELEPHONE MARKET WITH 7 HOURS ENFORCED TERMINATION TIME (100 Simulations)
Every Student May Hold Two Adjacent Offers
Psychology Model 20 Students May Hold 2 Offers for 2 Hours Until 1 Hour Before the Deadline Until the Deadline Every Firm First Issues Offers to Students Who Like It Best
Mean time to termination 7:43 7:53 8:01 8:08 7:36
Standard deviations :22 :10 :10 :07 :37
Mean time by which 90% of students have received at least one offer 1:02 2:11 2:22 2:33 :57
Mean time by which 99% of students have received at least one offer 5:07 7:06 7:37 7:51 5:23
Mean time of blocking firms 1:58 3:25 6:32 12:77 2:34
Standard deviations .74 1.26 1.61 2.27 1.02
Mean number of blocking students 16:67 29:88 47:74 77:76 15:74
Standard deviations 7.73 9.80 11.26 11.57 8.06
Mean number of unmatched students .88 1.09 1.52 1.69 .78
Mean number of unmatched firms .87 1.07 1.41 1.52 .78



TABLE 4:
HOURLY PROGRESS OF THE PSYCHOLOGY MODEL TELEPHONE MARKET
(Means of 100 Simulations)
Hour Number of Students With at Least One Offer Number of Students With An Offer From the Firm They Will Ultimately Matched With Number of Offers Made Number of Offers Not Rejected Immediately
0 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00
1 178.47 104.13 400.08 278.06
2 191.24 140.52 531.96 333.90
3 194.83 161.12 602.36 360.04
4 196.50 174.59 648.58 375.70
5 197.41 184.64 681.79 386.80
6 198.02 192.46 707.38 395.01
7 198.37 198.37 727.89 400.99
8 199.11 199.11 786.35 401.73
9 199.12 199.12 786.79 401.74



TABLE 5:
NUMBER OF STUDENTS & THE CHOICES THEY MATCH WITH (Means of 100 Simulations):
NUMBER OF STUDENTS WHO MATCH WITH CHOICE i
PSYCHOLOLOGY MODEL
Choice i That Students Match With Medical Model Psychology Model Modified Psychology Model: 20 Students May Hold 2 Offers for 2 Hours Students May Hold 2 Adjacent Offers Until 1 Hour Before the Deadline Every Student May Hold 2 Adjacent Offers Until the Deadline Firms First Issue Offers to Students Who Like Them Best
1 50.50 41.02 36.24 30.61 23.98 42.57
2 36.78 31.57 28.74 24.84 20.01 32.05
3 27.62 25.54 24.12 22.06 19.07 25.33
4 20.97 20.74 20.07 18.49 16.55 20.84
5 16.17 16.88 16.50 16.24 15.10 16.38
6 11.75 13.21 13.58 13.59 13.19 12.67
7 9.03 10.57 11.14 11.78 11.43 10.17
8 6.53 8.22 8.88 9.60 10.50 8.20
9 5.20 6.62 7.33 8.39 9.22 6.79
10 3.93 5.40 6.29 7.14 8.42 4.85
11 2.91 4.30 5.20 6.29 7.69 4.60
12 2.30 3.63 4.50 5.95 7.31 3.55
13 1.71 2.70 3.63 4.58 5.92 2.70
14 1.27 2.30 2.94 3.95 5.34 2.11
15 .86 1.53 2.34 3.26 5.41 1.72
16 .80 1.44 2.13 3.12 4.63 1.42
17 .50 1.04 1.53 2.69 4.23 .95
18 .44 .85 1.31 2.14 3.63 .98
19 .37 .76 1.23 2.07 3.93 .83
20 .35 .80 1.21 1.69 2.75 .51
Unmatched .01 .88 1.09 1.52 1.69 .78



TABLE 6:
MEDICAL & PSYCHOLOGY MARKET SIMULATIONS: VARYING THE CORRELATION OF PREFERENCES
(Students Have Preferences Over All 50 Firms; 100 Simulations)
PREFERENCES
Case 1: Students Have Uncorrelated Random Preferences; Firms Have Uncorrelated Random Preferences Case 2: Students Have Uncorrelated Random Preferences; Firms Have Identical Preferences Case 3: Students Have Identical Preferences; Firms Have Identical Preferences Case 4: Students Have Identical Preferences; Firms Have Uncorrelated Random Preferences
Medical Market Psychology Market Medical Market Psychology Market Medical Market Psychology Market Medical Market Psychology Market
Mean* Time to Termination 22:53 8:39 25:09 18:10 20:46 17:12 13:16 8:29
Standard Deviations 12:03 :43 :45 :14 :18 :17 2:18 :32
Mean Time By Which 90% of Students Have Received An Offer 1:09 1:09 22:06 16:10 18:51 15:12 1:18 1:18
Mean Time By Which 99% of Students Have Received An Offer 7:02 6:21 25:50 17:57 20:36 16:58 7:53 6:52
Mean Number of Blocking Firms 0 2:23 0 47:75 0 37.1 0 .68
Standard Deviations .85 2.05 .68
Mean Number of Blocking Students 0 31 0 151.13 0 156.13 0 1:72
Standard Deviations 12.83 3.71 7.48 2.23

*The corresponding medians are very close to the means.




TABLE 7:
MEDICAL MODEL TELEPHONE WITH VARYING NUMBER OF FIRMS & INFINITELY MANY PHONES:
200 STUDENTS & 200 POSITIONS TO BE FILLED (100 Simulations)
Number of Firms
2 5 10 20 50 100 200
Mean time to termination at a stable outcome 1:20 3:40 5:27 7:17 8:47 10:31 11:13
Standard deviations :24 1:22 2:34 3:27 3:19 5:41 4:49
Median time to termination 1:20 3:33 4:46 6:23 8:18 9:14 10:07
Mean time by which 90% of students have received an offer :10 :21 :27 :31 :34 :35 :35
Mean time by which 99% of students have received an offer :40 1:32 1:59 2:32 3:10 3:22 3:58
Longest time to termination 3:05 7:45 15:08 24:24 18:39 30:51 26:52
Shortest time to termination :40 1:26 2:32 2:04 3:52 2:53 3:29


ENDNOTES

[Click on note numbers to return to the text at the note.]

1.As far as we know, turnaround time has not attracted prior attention as an aspect of market clearing. But it plays a large role in strategic models of bargaining, which have been incorporated in market models (cf. Rubinstein 1982, Osborne and Rubinstein, 1990). Time plays an indirect role in these bargaining models, as attention is primarily given to equilibria in which transactions are made without delay (but in which the threat of delay influences transaction terms). In the markets we consider the delays are actually experienced.

2.Economists at American universities may want to think of the market for new assistant professors of Economics, in which a high proportion of transactions are made in the first few months of each calendar year. At many universities, each offer a department wishes to make requires separate approval by the Dean, so the turnaround time at some universities is better measured in days than in hours. The effective length of this market, in terms of how many times a new offer can be made following a rejection by a previous candidate, is further shortened by the fact that there is no uniform time until which offers must be left open, so candidates who do not receive their most preferred offers in the first "round" may have already accepted less preferred offers before better offers might be forthcoming. This of course engenders strategic behavior on both sides of the market. We will see that, even with a uniform time until which offers must be left open, related incentives for strategic behavior arise.

3.These markets have been analyzed as two-sided matching markets (see Roth and Sotomayor, 1990, for an overview of the theory, and Crawford, 1991, for a paper which makes clear why such models are particularly suited to the analysis of labor markets.) See Bergstrom and Bagnoli (1993) and Pollak (1994) for the use of matching models to study marriage markets, and Collins and Krishna (1993) for analysis of matching procedures for Harvard dormitory rooms.

4.The positions offered by each employer in such a market are divided into categories, if necessary, in which each position is identical (e.g. first year general internal medicine). The salary is part of the job description, fixed in advance. So applicants do not have to negotiate once they are matched, and can therefore determine their preferences in a non-contingent way.

5.Roth (1984) showed that the algorithm adopted in the early 1950's to organize the American entry level market for physicians (the National Resident Matching Program) was equivalent to the deferred acceptance procedure. By the early 1980's, the presence of married couples in the market had prompted changes in the algorithm which made this equivalence only approximate. Substantial further changes in this market in the late 1980's and early 1990's make the approximation rougher still, and are discussed in Roth (1996), as part of a design effort commissioned by the NRMP.

6.As one program director said to us, "you see these people again."

7.They could also use their judgement to modify the preferences, and indicated they would move the candidate ranked 12 ahead of numbers 10 and 11.

8.These directors indicated that they were careful not to pressure students to reveal their preferences, but that "the savviest candidates always do" reveal if a program is their first choice. We also heard of directors telling students that, while they would not ask if their program was the student's first choice, it would be most helpful to know should the student wish to say.

9.Also, the candidate ranked number 1 was a minority candidate who it was thought would have many offers from top places, and so would decide quickly.

10.Note that this change of plans is something that can happen in a decentralized market in which firms make decisions sequentially, but not in the centralized markets in which firms submit an entire preference list at one time.

11.It is an equilibrium for job candidates to behave in this way, because if all others do, then any candidate who allowed his offer to expire would face a market in which virtually all positions had been taken.

12.The APPIC rules for the aftermarket say only that offers may have "short but reasonable deadlines" (rule 9b). This is a bit coy, in that offers made, say, five minutes before the deadline need only remain open for five minutes.

13.This definition of stability appears to account only for coalitions of size one or two, but in fact accounts for coalitions of any size--i.e. stable matchings are in the core (see Roth and Sotomayor, 1990).

14.For other uses of random models of matching see Roth and Vande Vate (1990,1991), Blum Roth and Rothblum (forthcoming), and Roth and Rothblum (1996).

15.The revealed part of the preferences may also be "over-revealed" in the sense that the revealed preferences are always strict, while an agent who is in fact indifferent between two choices may have chosen arbitrarily between them. However, this applies equally to the centralized and decentralized procedures.

16.So an employer appears on a student's preference list if and only if the student appears on the employer's preference list. This is essentially an implementation of APPIC Rule 2, which has the effect that a student is not put in the position of waiting for an offer which has no possibility of being made. The expected number of applicants to each firm in this simulation is (2/5)200 = 80. The parameters make the simulated market larger than a typical psychology specialty submarket, and smaller than a typical medical specialty submarket.

17.Note that the average number of offers made in column 3 stops being so informative at later times, since many simulations terminate before the final hours--e.g. 15 of these 100 simulations terminated in under 10 hours.

18.After the end of hour 7 no more information calls are made in the simulation, so the only calls are made by firms with vacant positions.

19.Because any firm F which has no positions vacant when the deadline expires has already been rejected by each worker it prefers to its current assignments, and each worker who made such a rejection must be holding (or have already accepted) an offer it prefers to firm F.

20.In these simulations each student who applies to a firm has a .05 probability of ranking that firm first, so the probability that none of a firm's top 10 candidates will rank it first is .6. In the (unlikely) event that more than 4 of a firm's top 10 candidates rank it first, the simulation has the firm make offers to the 4 most preferred of these. Since firms have 4 positions, each firm would ordinarily make its initial offers to its first four choices, so the only change of behavior will be when a firm makes one of its initial offers to the candidates it ranks 5 through 10.

21.Consider a married student whose first choice is clear, but for whom the differences between the second and third choice are less clear, with the third choice being near the spouse's family. To make a decision between the second and third choice might involve a family fight, which can be avoided by delaying in the hope that an offer from the first choice will arrive. Note that there would be additional reasons for delay in a market in which the terms of employment can be negotiated--then multiple offers could be held to improve the negotiating position of a worker in relation to each of the firms making offers.

22.Although 20 students are potential delayers, the mean number of actual delayers in the simulations reported below is 16.88, since some potential delayers never receive a second offer.

23.If a student holding e.g. her 3rd and 4th choices receives an offer from her 2nd choice, the simulation has her continuing to hold two offers, but now her 2nd and 3rd. This happens on average only 1.12 times per simulation. A student holding two offers immediately releases them both if she gets a non-adjacent preferred offer, or if she gets an offer from her first choice.

24.These simulations are different from the first set of simulations with delays in two ways. First, more students may potentially be involved in delays. Second, the delays may be longer. The second factor has a greater effect than the first, because although every student may potentially be involved in the second kind of delay, they never in fact participate in a delay unless they get an offer adjacent in their preferences to the one they are holding. The mean number of students to whom this happened in the simulations was 23.51.

25.Recall that, on average, only 24 students were involved in such delays. But there is sufficiently little parallel processing going on in the later hours of the market that this completely shut it down. To take the phase change metaphor further, these markets start out liquid (in the parallel processing phase), then "freeze" as they become serial. When workers hold multiple offers, the market may freeze solid.

26.More comprehensive measures are necessarily a little complex, since we have made no assumptions which permit us to compare the welfare of a firm when it fills its positions with, say, choices 2,3,4, and 5, and when it fills them with choices 1,2,3, and 7.

27.Exactly which programs are unmatched is random, and even highly regarded programs are not immune (e.g. a program which is the second choice of every student can still be rejected right at the deadline by a student who has just gotten an offer from his first choice).

28.The mean number of offers required to reach a stable outcome when all preferences are uncorrelated (case 1) is 1015, but when students' preferences are perfectly correlated (case 4) it is 800.

29.We also studied partially correlated preferences, as follows. For a firm's preferences, assign to each student j the number j + Rj, where Rj is a random number drawn from a normal distribution with mean 0 and variance M. The firm prefers a student with a lower number j+Rj to one with a higher number k+Rk. When the variance M = 0, this gives us the identical, perfectly correlated preferences considered in Table 6. As M goes to infinity, the original numbers j diminish in importance and in the limit we get the case of uncorrelated random preferences. The results of these simulations show, as we might expect, that as the correlation of the preferences increases from zero to one, the behavior of the markets move continuously from one extreme to the other in Table 6. The most marked effects occur with the highest correlations of firms' preferences.

30.Consider, e.g., U.S. markets for residential housing.

31.Of course different agents in a market may face different effective lengths, depending on their own turnaround time.

32.For example, in recent years there has been a growth of "early admission" programs for college admission, in which colleges admit students in December (instead of in April) in return for a commitment to withdraw applications to other colleges and attend (see e.g. Arenson, 1996).

33.Roth and Xing (1994) note that there are a number of other reasons for offers to be made earlier and earlier, and one of these has recently been explored at some length by Li and Rosen (1996).

34.Thus, for example, I am not sanguine about the prospects for the latest market reorganization proposed in the market for Federal court clerks (see Becker, Breyer, and Calabresi, 1994). The rules proposed there seem likely to promote behavior that will lead to a very short effective length of the market.